- Quotes from the book by P. Adamson and J Ganeri: Classical Indian Philosophy: a History of Philosophy Without any Gaps. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Volume 5 (2020),
- Quotes from Yuriy Zavhorodniy´s review of the book “Classical Indian Philosophy" by P. Adamson and J Ganer in Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2 (2021),
- Quotes from other Ukrainian research papers in support of the methodology of the Eastern Philosophies Researchers Society,
- Books on the History of Indian Philosophy referred to by Yuriy Zavhorodniy.
We can't help but mention one important and pleasant circumstance. The electronic version of the book can be found publicly available online.
Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021 page 81
Yuriy Zavhorodniy: Relevance of the book by P. Adamson and J. Ganeri
In Ukraine, if we do not take into account the journalistic publications of Yakov Novitsky “Essays on Indian Philosophy” (mid-nineteenth century), have never published review publications on the history of Indian philosophy. We hope that the experience of “Classical Indian Philosophy” will be taken into account by those who will sooner or later prepare such publications in our country.
Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021. page 81
At first glance, the title of the book may seem standard, ie one that does not raise questions. But is that so? It is worth stopping here and referring to the titles of well-known publications devoted to the history of Indian philosophy. It turns out that, starting from the origins of the academic study of Indian philosophy, for a long time there was not a single book dedicated to it, in the title of which the phrase "Indian philosophy" would contain the clarification "classical". This trend continues today, although in recent decades you can find essays on "Classical Indian Philosophy" Perhaps the title of the publication by P. Adamson and J. Ganeri reflects certain trends in world historical and philosophical indology of recent decades. Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021 p 69
Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021 p 73
Yuriy Zavhorodniy: Stages in the development of knowledge
The book contains a chronological table which consists of seven categories and covers the period from the origins of Indian philosophy until the 1970s, containing the name of the philosopher, his years of life and the names of key works. In the main part of the book instead, specific dates are extremely rare. Apparently, the authors deliberately made most of the chronological specifics in the summary table, so as not to distract the reader from the presentation of purely philosophical material. The authors note that the table is taken from the Oxford Handbook of Indian Philosophy (2017), in which J. Gunnery was the editor. Given Ganeri's involvement in both editions, it is not entirely clear why the chronological table covers the entire period of Indian philosophy, and not the one present in the title of the book.
Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021. page 81
In present modern philosophical Ukrainian studies a special place in the process of institutionalization of Ukrainian philosophy's history is assigned to Professor VS Gorsky's scientific contribution, where the culturological approach plays an essential role. The last one allows: 1) to research exactly the sophian dimension distinguishing between “philosophic theory” and “philosophic wisdom”: 2) to analyze the historical and philosophical sphere of the philosophical dimension of culture as a history of values and both meaningful and vital ideals and ideas. 3) to eliminate the opposition of religio-theological and philosophical interpretation of the same texts. 4) to broaden a range of sources, including nonverbal ones, which are added into historical and philosophical analysis, (works of monumental painting and architecture) become a source of historical and philosophical analysis.
Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021, p 77
The Mahabharata is exclusive and unique. Obviously, this opinion. deserve attention and revives the discussion about the source base of ancient Indian philosophy. The Mahabharata is one of the most important texts for the Authors because it has a built-in part called the Song of the Lord - Bhagavad Gita. If the status of a philosophical text is recognized exclusively by the Bhagavad Gita, as the author do, then it turns out that the philosopher in it is the Absolute, the Lord, because most of the words belong to Him, Kṛṣṇa. Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021, p 75
The book mentions the ancient wisdom of the Vedas and the Upanishads. It also mentions the not human origins of wisdom in the Charaka-Samhita, one of the oldest texts of Ayurveda, there it is stated that it conveys “wisdom first received from the gods, the mythical Ashwin”, the transforming nature of wisdom: “the wise become immortal" (quote from Ken Upanishad) ; wisdom can go hand in hand with liberation when it comes to the truth of the Vedas .In the above examples, the sage and wisdom is in the highest state that a person can achieve.Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021, p 76
Buddha and Mahavira are not philosophers for us, but figures of a different ontological level or status in another form of interaction with the world, which turns out to be inherent in both divine beings and man. Sententiae, Volume XL, Issue 2, 2021, p 77
- wisdom (sage) ,
- philosophical knowledge (philosopher)
- other not philosophical, but also traditional knowledge (other intellectuals).
Can the clash between a Vedanta philosopher and a Buddhist critic really be resolved on the basis of commonly held assumptions? Or are they just talking past one another, using the same words in very different ways? Shankara’s commentary on the Brahma Sutra answers this question. He admits that people disagree about the qualities of Brahman but insists that we all have a common idea of it, which gives us only “partial” knowledge. As proof, Śankara offers an etymology of the word Brahman itself: “its very nature (svabhav̄a) is said to consist in what is eternal, pure and consciousness; bound up with the omniscient and the omnipotent. For the meanings such as ‘being eternal’ and ‘being pure’ are derived from semantic analysis of the word Brahman, these meanings following from the verbal root bṛh. Here we have another reminder of the importance of Sanskrit grammar for philosophers. It was commonly held that linguistic analysis (called vyutpatti or nirvacana) can explain why we use certain words for certain things. On the basis of its verbal root, the word dharma was claimed to mean “that which upholds.” Likewise, here, Śankara conjectures that the term brahman is derived from the verbal root bṛh, meaning “to grow.” This shows that brahman is in some way maximally great. It is, so to speak, all grown up. This might seem a rather flimsy response to the skeptic, but Śankara has a second and more formidable move to make, one that will again remind us of European philosophy. He argues that the paradox of inquiry poses no threat to an investigation about brahman, because this is a case where we have direct knowledge. As he says, “Every one knows of the existence of his own self, and does not think ‘I am not.’ If the existence of one’s own self were not perfectly well known, any one of us could think, ‘I am not.’
The parallel with European thinkers like Augustine and Descartes is almost too obvious to need emphasizing. But unlike Descartes, with his famous “I think, therefore I am,” Śankara does not use immediate knowledge of one’s own existence to refute global skepticism. He just wants to show that the inquiry into brahman promised at the beginning of the sūtra is indeed possible. He alludes to the Upaniṣadic statement, “You are that (tat tvam asi),” which he interprets as meaning “This self is brahman.” Since it cannot be doubted that there is a self, and since the self is brahman, neither can there be doubt concerning brahman. There is, in other words, something for us to investigate. But if we have immediate knowledge of the self, or brahman, why do we need to inquire into it? Because our intimate awareness of brahman does not include an understanding of its true nature. As Śankara observes, there are intense disagreements about the self, with the materialists and “common folk” assuming that the self is the body, the Buddhists thinking it is just the flow of our cognitions, the Nyāya thinking it is an agent and subject of experience distinct from the body, the Sāṃkhya agreeing that it differs from the body but denying that it is an agent, and so on. Our point and Śankara’s point, is that there is indeed plenty of dispute on this topic, and hence plenty of reason to engage in the philosophical investigation undertaken in the sūtra. (Chapter 20)
Bilimoria, P and Rayner, A (Ed.). (2018) History of Indian Philosophy. London and New York:Routledge.https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315666792
Chatterjee, S and Datta, D (1948) An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Calcutta: University of Calcutta.
Colebrooke, HT (1837) On the Philosophy of the Hindu. In HT Colebrooke. Miscellaneous Essays (Vol. I, pp. 227-419). London: WH Allen.
Cowell, EB, and Gough, AE (Trans.) (2000) The Sarva-darśana-sangraha of Mādhavāchārya Review of the Different Systems of Hindu Philosophy. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Dasgupta, S (1991) A History of Indian Philosophy(Vol. I). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Franco, E. (2013) On the Periodization and Historiography of Indian Philosophy. In E. Franco (Ed.). Periodization and Historiography of Indian Philosophy(pp. 1-34). Vienna: Verein “Sammulng de Nobili, Arbeitsgemeinschaft für Indologie und Religionsforschung”, Institute for Sudanese, Tibetan and Buddhist Studies of the University of Vienna.
Frauwallner, EVM (1997) History of Indian Philosophy(Vol. 1). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass,
Ganeri, J. (2001) Philosophy in Classical India. The proper Work of Reason. London: Routledge.
Ganeri, J. (2013) Well-Ordered Science and Indian Epistemic Cultures: Toward a Polycentered History of Science,Isis, 104(2), 348-359.https://doi.org/10.1086/670953
Ganeri, J. (Ed.). (2017) The Oxford handbook of Indian Philosophy.Oxford, & New York: Oxford University Press
Gupta, B. (2012) An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. Perspectives on Reality, Knowledge, and Freedom.New York, London: N Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/97802038061280
Hadot, P (2002) What is Ancient Philosophy? Cambridge, London: The Belknap Press & Harvard.
Hiriyanna, M.(1994) Outlines of Indian Philosophy.Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Krishna, D. (1991) Indian Philosophy. A Counter Perspective. Delhi, Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Maas, Ph.D. A. (2013) A Concise Historiography of Classical Yoga Philosophy. In E. Franco (Ed.). Periodization and Historiography of Indian Philosophy(pp. 53-90). Vienna: Verein “Sammlung de Nobili, Arbeitsgemeinschaft für Indologie und Religionsforschung”, Institute for Sudanese, Tibetan and Buddhist Studies of the University of Vienna.
Mohanty, JN (2000) Classical Indian Philosophy.Lanham, Md Rowman & Littlefield.
Müller, FM (1899) The Six Systems of Indian Philosophy.New York: Longmans Green; L. and Bombay
Potter, KH (Ed.). (2019) Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies.http://faculty.washington.edu/kpotter/ xencyclo.html
Radhakrishnan, S. (1948) Indian Philosophy(Vol. I). London: George Allen & Unwin.
Sarma, D. (2011) Classical Indian Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.
Sharma, Ch. (2009) A Critical Survey of Indian Philosophy.Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Smart, N. (1967). Indian Philosophy. In P. Edwards (Ed.),The Encyclopedia of Philosophy(Vol. 4, 155-169). New York: The Macmillan Company and Free Press, London: Collier-Macmillan Limited.
Warder, AK (1998) .A Course in Indian Philosophy.Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.